10 September 2006

More on the Mean

To recap from yesterday...

The Doctrine of the Mean
Actions (and emotions) have 'parameters' (what objects, when, how, how much, for the sake of what), and, when an action (or emotion) goes wrong, it does so because it is too much or too little with respect to at least one parameter.

Hursthouse
Sometimes an action (or emotion) goes wrong because of an error in quality, not quantity. Consider the emotion of fear, and the parameter of 'what objects'. A virtuous person fears (let us suppose) only death, trauma, and severe pain. Consider now a 'fearless phobic' who fears only mice, the dark, and open spaces. His error is not one of quantity, because he too fears precisely three sorts of things. His error, then, is one of quality.

Curzer
We should probably say that a 'fearless phobic' is mentally ill, not vicious. But putting this point aside, we can say that such a person does indeed go wrong in quantity: he fears mice (and the others) too much, and he fears death (and the others) too little.

Pearson
It is odd to say that a person fears mice 'too much', when what we mean is that he should not fear them at all. The reason is that a statement of the form, "He F's X too much", carries with it the implicature that some degree of F toward X is appropriate. The oddness of "He fears mice too much" indicates that the difference between fearing mice and not fear them is not a difference in degree.

But now to carry on:

(1) I wonder if Pearson's objection doesn't depend on an artefact of language. 'Too much' means 'more than one should'. Thus, "He fears mice too much" means "He fears mice more than he should (fear mice)." It smuggles in the object, when we wanted to say that the right amount of fear toward the object is none. But that phrasing is inessential. We could easily say, rather: "He shows too much fear in fearing mice", which carries with it no unwanted implicature.

(2) Surely it is right to say that someone "shows too much fear in fearing mice", and also surely the fearless phobic example is contrived and not a serious example in ethics. This needs to be accounted for. I propose the the following.

As regards the parameter of "what objects"-- we do not evaluate actions (or emotions) in isolation, but we interpret each as an expression of a 'distribution'. For instance, as regards fear, we think that a person's fear of something should be proportionate to the actual threat or danger it poses (thus Aristotle, 1115b7-14); furthermore, we presume that the usual principles of rational preference should apply to this (e.g. transitivity--if someone fears a snarling dog more than a mild dog, and a wolf more than a snarling dog, he is rationally bound to fear a wolf more than a mild dog.) So we view his reactions of fear as reasonably and typically distributed in a series: more fear for objectively more threatening objects, less fear for objectively less threatening objects. And that is why the 'fearless phobic' is an unreal example: someone who feared a mouse should reasonably fear even more a heavily armed enemy coming at you in battle.

Now it seems natural to suppose that there will be a relationship between (i) degree of fear as shown towards an object that should be feared, and (ii) extent of distribution of one's fear. E.g. someone who fears a snarling dog too much might fear a mild dog when he shouldn't; someone who fears a wolf too little might fail to fear a snarling dog when he should. Strong emotion makes the distribution broad; weak emotion makes it narrow. We correctly interpret fear toward an inappropriate object, then, in terms of a distribution we take that fear to display. (This is one way in which we view actions as expressions of character.) That is why it is right to say such things as "He shows too much fear in fearing mice", that is, the excess fear he shows toward appropriate objects of fear spills over, even, to things that are not fearful at all.

This notion of a 'extent of distribution' of fear provides a reply, too, to the objection that Ben Miller raised in a comment: If not fearing a mouse is the mean--he asked--and fearing a mouse is excessive, then what counts as the contrary extreme? What counts as deficiency of fear in this case--a negative fear of mice??

In reply to this one might deny that, for Aristotle, all particular actions (and emotions) have erroneous extremes on either side of them (why couldn't Milo's diet ever be to eat all 10 minae?), even if habits leading to extremes (i.e. in some parameter or other) are matched by habits leading to deficiencies.

But perhaps a better reply is available, using the notion of a distribution. Someone who fears too little as regards the 'object' parameter will typically distribute his fear too narrowly. Thus objects that should be on the border are more remote from being feared than they should be. For instance, if it's appropriate to have slight fear for a snarling dog, but not a mild dog, then, as a dog changes from mild to snarling, one should appropriately change from not fearing to fearing it. But if a person generally fears things too little, he won't begin to fear a mild dog that begins to snarl--and from this we might say that, even though he did not fear the mild dog at all, still he feared it less than he should, in the precise sense that he did not place it close enough in the scale to objects that should appropriately be feared.

(Granted, some objects shouldn't be conceived of in relation to the scale at all, e.g. my easy chair, or an earthquake. But that's just to say that these are not 'human' objects of fear, and inappropriate fear as regards such things constitutes mental illness, not moral badness. Again, see 1115b7-9.)

5 comments:

Macuquinas d' Oro said...

In managing his fear and anger, the virtuous man must do several things that do not involve hitting a mean. Certainly he must control the intensity of his feeling with a view to avoiding extremes, but he also must make sure that his emotions are directed towards the right people on the right occasions for the right reasons. NE II. vi gives us this list twice.

The right people, the right occasions, the right reason(s) are not continua. It makes no sense to speak about hitting a mean in these matters. The man who is chronically angry over trivial matters, whatever else he does or doesn’t get angry over, goes wrong because his anger targets the wrong kind of thing. The man who has little fear of fearful things because he wants to die goes wrong because he is without fear for the wrong reason. Nowhere in NE II-V that I am aware of is there even an effort to concoct a “mean” that might seem to apply in such matters.

The problem is that NE II. vi seem unaware of the complexity of its own theory of virtue when it asserts, as it does at 1107a7-9 , that moral virtue is essentially a matter of hitting a mean. Certainly it is necessarily a matter of hitting the mean in intensity of feeling ( and perhaps, in a different sense, in action ), but in other key “parameters” there is no continuum of choices and no mean to hit. So moral virtue is not simply and essentially a prohairetic hexis that aims at hitting a mean. NE II.vi gets it wrong.

papabear said...

Certainly he must control the intensity of his feeling with a view to avoiding extremes.

How does one control the intensity of feeling? Are you talking about something akin to repression?

Certainly it is necessarily a matter of hitting the mean in intensity of feeling ( and perhaps, in a different sense, in action ), but in other key “parameters” there is no continuum of choices and no mean to hit.
Does the virtue modify a power/emotion? Or are all virtues simply a mode of choice? If it is the former, then does it make sense to talk of a continuum of choices?

Macuquinas d' Oro said...

Papabear,

We train soldiers facing combat to control their fear. Surely Aristotle doesn’t think that andreia is some sort of innate disposition that we either just have or lack. I’ve trained boxers. Young men who are initially very apprehensive about the ring gradually learn from their training and their ring experience to manage their fear. The fear never completely goes away--nor should it, because the ring is a dangerous place--but young fighters, like young soldiers, learn to concentrate on their job and set the fear aside. Andreia comes not from trying to extirpate or repress the emotion, but from schooling and educating it to focus on what really is dangerous. Inevitably that moderates the emotion.

If I understand your second point, let me respond by saying that I agree that the NE II. vi. does not do a good job telling us what a moral virtue is. It is a faculty skilful at hitting the mean ( stochastike tou mesou ), it finds and selects ( heuriskein kai haireithai ) the mean, and finally it is prohairetike hexis residing (?) in a mean state relative to us…( 1106b36 ff.). What do you take a prohairetike hexis to be ?

papabear said...


We train soldiers facing combat to control their fear. Surely Aristotle doesn’t think that andreia is some sort of innate disposition that we either just have or lack. I’ve trained boxers. Young men who are initially very apprehensive about the ring gradually learn from their training and their ring experience to manage their fear. The fear never completely goes away--nor should it, because the ring is a dangerous place--but young fighters, like young soldiers, learn to concentrate on their job and set the fear aside. Andreia comes not from trying to extirpate or repress the emotion, but from schooling and educating it to focus on what really is dangerous. Inevitably that moderates the emotion.

Yes, emotion being submitted to the guidance of reason. I just think the use of the word "control" I think is problematic.

If NE II is not clear about what moral virtue it is, perhaps we should keep in mind the fact that for Aristotle the virtues are interconnected. Still, can one virtue be distinguished from another by the power it modifies? I would say yes, they are not simply modes of choice which are distinguished only logically.

Macuquinas d' Oro said...

One thing that has never been explained to me is how a virtuous man, for example, a courageous man, can be said to aim at a MEAN IN ACTION. Aristotle’s paradigm of the man of andreia is a soldier in combat. I can imagine a brave soldier in the midst of some sort of terrible combat, but I cannot imagine him looking for some sort of mean course to resolve his predicament. That is just too strange. It is almost ridiculous to imagine him saying, “I mustn’t do too much or too little here.” The brave soldier knows instinctively that he needs to do whatever the situation requires of him to save to save his men and himself, and that may well be extreme ( heroic ) action. As I said, I can make no sense of aiming at “moderate action” in this situation. ( But perhaps someone else can?)

Aiming at moderate emotion, on the other hand, i.e., controlling himself emotionally, I do understand, and I think it is part of the experience of brave soldiers in combat. They pause, sometimes repeatedly, to make sure that the fear and anger they are experiencing does not run away with them and drive them into fatal errors.

In general I’ve always found that the Doctrine of the Mean had more intuitive appeal when we apply it on the emotional side of the ledger and are looking for some sort of mean or moderate state in the intensity of fear or anger or sorrow or desire. But virtuous action that is also said to aim at a MEAN IN ACTION is much more problematic.